natural theology

We have just published a new book that summarizes the ideas of this site. Free at Scientific Theology, or, if you wish to support this project, buy at Scientific Theology: A New Vision of God

Contact us: Click to email
vol III Development:

Chapter 3: Cybernetics

page 5: Mathematics

Form and formalism

We might say that science is an answer to Parmenides' question: how can we have certain knowledge in a changing world? His answer has become standard: there is a central, eternal complete core of being which can be truly known by 'the path of conviction', then there is the ephemeral world of day to day events which we know through 'the way of mortals'. John Palmer - Parmenides

Through Plato and others, mathematics became associated with the way of conviction, since it appeared to deliver indisputable truths. In his dialogue Parmenides Plato expounds (through the character Socrates) his theory of forms, that 'there is a single, eternal, unchanging, indivisible, and non-sensible form corresponding to every predicate or property.' Samuel Rickless: Plato's Parmenides

We can identify two opposing concepts about the nature of mathematics: Platonism maintains that 'there are abstract mathematical objects whose existence is independent of us and our language, thought, and practices. . . . Mathematical truths are therefore discovered, not invented.' The alternative view is that mathematical statements are all our own work, invented rather than discovered. Øystein Linnebo

David Hilbert and Formalism

This second approach is often called formalism. Formalist mathematicians are not concerned with the reality or unreality of mathematical truths, but see mathematics as a field of formal games played according to certain axioms and rules of inference that sometimes lead to interesting results, and sometimes not. From this point of view, the only constraint on mathematics is that its axioms and rules be consistent and lead to consistent conclusions. Mathematical 'existence' is equivalent to formal consistency.

This approach was espoused by David Hilbert, among others, who was impressed by the discoveries of Georg Cantor, which he called 'Cantor's Paradise'. Although Cantor's transfinite numbers seem incredible at first sight, they involve no inconsistency. Hilbert saw these numbers as a hierarchy of function spaces, and von Neumann discovered that one form of function space, Hilbert space, is the natural habitat for quantum mechanics. Cantor's paradise - Wikipedia, von Neumann: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics

Hilbert thought that the formal method would be so powerful that ultimately every mathematical problem would be solved. Gödel and Turing showed that this was not to be so: there are limits, known as incompleteness and incomputability, on formal mathematics. There are mathematical problems that have no consistent answer. Here we see these facts, when applied to the physical world, as the foundation of uncertainty and creativity. Gödel's incompleteness theorems - Wikipedia, Turing machine - Wikipedia

Eugene Wigner and the 'unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics'
Einstein 1954 to Besso: 'I consider it quite possible that physics cannot be based on the field principle, ie on continuous structures. In that case nothing remains of my entire castle in the air, gravitation theory included. Kevin Brown: Reflections of relativity

Wigner highlights the miraculous correspondence between mathematical symbolism and observations of the physical Universe: . . . the enormous usefulness of mathematics in the natural sciences is something bordering on the mysterious and there is no rational explanation for it. Eugene Wigner

Wigner's observation compels us to examine the relationship between mathematics and physics. Here I wish to suggest an explanation of Wigner's observation. The idea is essentially very simple. Science is devoted to detecting and connecting the fixed points of the Universe. Mathematics, on the other hand, represents the fixed points of a subset of the Universe, the mathematical community.

Insofar as the Universe is one and consistent, it is not surprising that we find a considerable degree of isomorphism or symmetry between these two sets of fixed points. The challenge here is to build a bridge from physics through the mathematical community to the Universe as a whole that clearly illustrates that symmetry. Symmetry - Wikipedia

Quantum mechanics has taught us that all the observable features of the Universe (upon which science is based) are quantized. Nevertheless, quantum mechanics assumes that the mechanism underlying these quantized observations can be represented by continuous mathematics. Here I suggest that this assumption is false, and that we can better describe the Universe by assuming that it is digital 'to the core'.

This digitization suggests that we can see the Universe as a logical, rather than a geometric continuum. The mathematical representation of a logical continuum is the Turing machine, a stepwise digital process that leads deterministically from an initial condition to a final condition. We may see such logical connections as the fixed points in the universal dynamics which form the goal and substance of science. Linear continuum - Wikipedia

I guess that the theorems requiring fixed points in a dynamical system are indifferent to the complexity of the system, and I postulate an isomorphism between the dynamics of the mathematical community and the dynamics of the world. I propose that this isomorphism explains the 'unreasonable effectiveness' of mathematics in the sciences.

Is the transfinite network isomorphic with mathematics?

Here we accept the formalist view of mathematics introduced by Hilbert. Hilbert's approach distinguishes mathematics from the study of observable reality and sees it as a game played with certain symbols and certain rules. The symbols cannot move themselves to implement the rules: all the action comes from the mathematicians (and their computers) manipulating fixed and invariant symbols according to the rules of their current game. Richard Zach

The mathematics industry, like any other, thus comprises workers (mathematicians) who 'do' the mathematics and their mathematical communications which may be conversations, lectures, papers, books, models or any other means of mathematical communication.

Although mathematicians talk about continuous and infinite entities like lines and real numbers, all their communication is symbolic, that is finite and quantized. Everything that a mathematician needs can therefore be represented by finite strings of symbols manipulated according to finite sets of rules. This situation is reflected in the mathematical literature, which is finite even if when it talks about infinite entities like the set of natural numbers.

The transfinite network provides us with a model of the whole mathematical process. Mathematicians themselves are represented in network by nodes, which are themselves networks of cells. molecules and so on. These networks have a certain cardinality, the cardinal of humanity. Mathematicians communicate with one another using mathematical protocols which enable them to encode and decode ideas like 'complex numbers', 'Hilbert space', 'differential and integral operators' and so on.

The transfinite network is a formal model of the Universe, able to formally model its own dynamics, including the mathematics industry. We use this insight to found the claim that the transfinite network is in effect isomorphic to mathematics. Like mathematics, it has no boundaries except formal consistency and the rate at which its operators can work.

(revised 8 January 2019)

Copyright:

You may copy this material freely provided only that you quote fairly and provide a link (or reference) to your source.

Further reading

Books

Click on the "Amazon" link below each book entry to see details of a book (and possibly buy it!)

von Neumann, John, and Robert T Beyer (translator), Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton University Press 1983 Jacket: '. . . a revolutionary book that caused a sea change in theoretical physics. . . . JvN begins by presenting the theory of Hermitean operators and Hilbert spaces. These provide the framework for transformation theory, which JvN regards as the definitive form of quantum mechanics. . . . Regarded as a tour de force at the time of its publication, this book is still indispensable for those interested in the fundamental issues of quantum mechanics.' 
Amazon
  back
Links
Cantor's paradise - Wikipedia, Cantor's paradise - Wikipedia, the fre encyclopedia, 'Cantor's paradise is an expression used by David Hilbert . . . in describing set theory and infinite cardinal numbers developed by Georg Cantor. The context of Hilbert's comment was his opposition to what he saw as L. E. J. Brouwer's reductive attempts to circumscribe what kind of mathematics is acceptable; see Brouwer–Hilbert controversy.' back
Eugene Wigner, The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences, 'The first point is that the enormous usefulness of mathematics in the natural sciences is something bordering on the mysterious and that there is no rational explanation for it. Second, it is just this uncanny usefulness of mathematical concepts that raises the question of the uniqueness of our physical theories.' back
Formalism (mathematics) - Wikipedia, Formalism (mathematics) - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia, 'In foundations of mathematics, philosophy of mathematics, and philosophy of logic, formalism is a theory that holds that statements of mathematics and logic can be thought of as statements about the consequences of certain string manipulation rules. For example, Euclidean geometry can be seen as a game whose play consists in moving around certain strings of symbols called axioms according to a set of rules called "rules of inference" to generate new strings. In playing this game one can "prove" that the Pythagorean theorem is valid because the string representing the Pythagorean theorem can be constructed using only the stated rules.' back
Gödel's incompleteness theorems - Wikipedia, Gödel's incompleteness theorems - Wikipedia, 'Gödel's incompleteness theorems are two theorems of mathematical logic that establish inherent limitations of all but the most trivial axiomatic systems capable of doing arithmetic. The theorems, proven by Kurt Gödel in 1931, are important both in mathematical logic and in the philosophy of mathematics. The two results are widely, but not universally, interpreted as showing that Hilbert's program to find a complete and consistent set of axioms for all of mathematics is impossible, giving a negative answer to Hilbert's second problem. The first incompleteness theorem states that no consistent system of axioms whose theorems can be listed by an "effective procedure" (e.g., a computer program, but it could be any sort of algorithm) is capable of proving all truths about the relations of the natural numbers (arithmetic). For any such system, there will always be statements about the natural numbers that are true, but that are unprovable within the system. The second incompleteness theorem, a corollary of the first, shows that such a system cannot demonstrate its own consistency.' back
Henry Mendel, Aristotle and Mathematics, back
John Palmer - Parmenides, Parmenides (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy), First published Fri Feb 8, 2008 ' Immediately after welcoming Parmenides to her abode, the goddess describes as follows the content of the revelation he is about to receive: You must needs learn all things,/ both the unshaken heart of well-rounded reality/ and the notions of mortals, in which there is no genuine trustworthiness./ Nonetheless these things too will you learn, how what they resolved/ had actually to be, all through all pervading. (Fr. 1.28b-32) ' back
Kevin Brown, Reflections on Relativity, By Maciej Ceglowski on January 27, 2012 Format: Paperback 'This wonderful book has long been available online, but I'm delighted to see that the author has chosen to publish it in physical form. This is the kind of book you really want to be able to flip through and fill with marginalia. I've been reading through it about once a year, and each time I find myself understanding it a little better. The author has a great gift for presenting challenging material in a way that remains accessible to those of us who haven't made it past calculus. Equal parts history, philosophy of science, and physics textbook, it's an absolute treasure, and I'm delighted to finally be able to give the author some money.' back
Linear continuum - Wikipedia, Linear continuum - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia, 'In the mathematical field of order theory, a continuum or linear continuum is a generalization of the real line. Formally, a linear continuum is a linearly ordered set S of more than one element that is densely ordered, i.e., between any two members there is another, and which "lacks gaps" in the sense that every non-empty subset with an upper bound has a least upper bound.' back
Øystein Linnebo, Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics, 'Platonism about mathematics (or mathematical platonism) is the metaphysical view that there are abstract mathematical objects whose existence is independent of us and our language, thought, and practices. Just as electrons and planets exist independently of us, so do numbers and sets. And just as statements about electrons and planets are made true or false by the objects with which they are concerned and these objects' perfectly objective properties, so are statements about numbers and sets. Mathematical truths are therefore discovered, not invented.' back
Richard Zach, Hilbert's Program (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy), 'In the early 1920s, the German mathematician David Hilbert (1862-1943) put forward a new proposal for the foundation of classical mathematics which has come to be known as Hilbert's Program. It calls for a formalization of all of mathematics in axiomatic form, together with a proof that this axiomatization of mathematics is consistent. The consistency proof itself was to be carried out using only what Hilbert called "finitary" methods. The special epistemological character of finitary reasoning then yields the required justification of classical mathematics.' back
Samuel Rickless, Plato' Parmenides, 'Plato's Parmenides consists in a critical examination of the theory of forms, a set of metaphysical and epistemological doctrines articulated and defended by the character Socrates in the dialogues of Plato's middle period (principally Phaedo, Republic II–X, Symposium). According to this theory, there is a single, eternal, unchanging, indivisible, and non-sensible form corresponding to every predicate or property. The theoretical function of these forms is to explain why things (particularly, sensible things) have the properties they do. Thus, it is by virtue of being in some way related to (i.e., by participating in, or partaking of) the form of beauty that beautiful things (other than beauty) are beautiful, it is by virtue of partaking of the form of largeness that large things are large, and so on. Fundamental to this theory is the claim that forms are separate from (at least in the sense of being not identical to) the things that partake of them.' back
Symmetry - Wikipedia, Symmetry - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia, 'Symmetry (from Greek συμμετρία symmetria "agreement in dimensions, due proportion, arrangement") in everyday language refers to a sense of harmonious and beautiful proportion and balance. In mathematics, "symmetry" has a more precise definition, that an object is invariant to a transformation, such as reflection but including other transforms too. Although these two meanings of "symmetry" can sometimes be told apart, they are related, so they are here discussed together.' back
Turing machine - Wikipedia, Turing machine - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia, A Turing machine is a hypothetical device that manipulates symbols on a strip of tape according to a table of rules. Despite its simplicity, a Turing machine can be adapted to simulate the logic of any computer algorithm, and is particularly useful in explaining the functions of a CPU inside a computer. The "machine" was invented in 1936 by Alan Turing[1][2] who called it an "a-machine" (automatic machine). The Turing machine is not intended as practical computing technology, but rather as a hypothetical device representing a computing machine. Turing machines help computer scientists understand the limits of mechanical computation.' back

www.naturaltheology.net is maintained by The Theology Company Proprietary Limited ACN 097 887 075 ABN 74 097 887 075 Copyright 2000-2019 © Jeffrey Nicholls